Just in time for a new school year, the September 2017 issue of Scholastic Art magazine features ten paintings that students should know, because they form part of “our collective cultural history.”
Surely a worthwhile undertaking for a publication aimed at middle school and high school visual art education programs—until one examines the works selected and what is written about them.
Legitimizing the Avant-Garde
Most troubling is that four of the magazine’s “10 Paintings to Know” are twentieth-century works that depart so radically from all prior standards that their art historical status is highly questionable. They are Pablo Picasso’s Dora Maar in an Armchair, Vasily Kandinsky’s Composition 8, Alma Thomas’s Splash Down Apollo 13, and Jean-Michel Basquiat’s Untitled (Skull). Two of the remaining ten (Georgia O’Keeffe’s Two Calla Lilies on Pink and Frida Kahlo’s The Two Fridas), though somewhat less radical, also date from the twentieth century. When one considers that art history encompasses millennia of picture-making, this is a staggering disproportion. Not one work from the Italian Renaissance or the Golden Age of Dutch painting or the rich tradition of landscape painting in China—much less work by our own Hudson River School or more recent examples by important American artists such as Thomas Eakins or Andrew Wyeth.
Still worse is the choice of Picasso’s savagely cubist portrait of Dora Maar for the issue’s cover—a choice that implies this painting is especially worth knowing. Why is such a visually repellent work considered worth knowing? Because—Scholastic Art tells its young readers—Picasso is among “the most influential 20th-century artists,” and cubism is “one of his most important contributions to modern art.”
What did that contribution consist of?—“divid[ing] subject matter into small, simplified forms” and “reject[ing] traditional perspective.” In the Dora Maar portrait, Picasso “reduces the subject’s face, hair, and body to a collection of geometric shapes” and “places her features in an asymmetrical arrangement, creating an off-balance version of a face” (an understatement if ever there were one!). Picasso also “embraced bright, arbitrary colors” such as “yellow for the face, red for the nose, and blue for the mouth.” On the larger questions of this bizarre painting’s impact on viewers and the dubious value of reducing the face of a beautiful woman (see photos of Dora Maar) to an arbitrary pattern of geometric shapes eerily akin to the wallpaper behind it, not a word is said. Nor does the article ask whether it is wise to regard such extreme stylistic distortions as a “contribution.”
Students are further misled by the poster enclosed with the issue. On one side is a large-scale reproduction of Picasso’s Woman with Yellow Hair, accompanied by this quote attributed to him below it: “Learn the rules like a pro so you can break them like an artist” (as if art were mainly a matter of breaking rules). The reverse of the poster displays Jean-Michel Basquiat’s Horn Players (1983). If Basquiat ever learned the rules, I’ve seen no evidence of it. In any case, are these the two most significant works from the whole of art history that students should have posted before them in the classroom?
What prompted the inclusion of Basquiat’s Untitled (Skull—which he appears to have misspelled as Scull) in “10 Paintings to Know”? Since the work dates from less than four decades ago, it cannot quite be said to have stood “the test of time” (one of Scholastic Art’s criteria for a work’s worth knowing about). Instead, his involvement with the New York City street art movement is cited, and the fact that his work was shown “in the city’s top art galleries.” Also noted is that, despite his death at the age of 27, “he is among the most commercially successful artists in history”—one of his paintings having been bought by a collector in May 2017 “for a record $110.5 million.” Nonetheless—the reader is informed—“many questions about his work [remain] unanswered.”
Not mentioned by Scholastic Art is the fact that Basquiat was a drug addict, whose premature death was due to a heroin overdose. Relevant questions about his work that remain are what on earth it means and how much of its chaotic aspect might be due to the drug’s psychedelic effects, rather than to any great creativity on his part. A further urgent question not raised by the magazine for students to consider is whether today’s art market is in fact a reliable indicator of artistic value. Finally, does the crude and confusing nature of Basquiat’s work really merit his presentation to students as a model for appreciation and emulation?1
Misconstruing Art of the Past
The one incontestable European masterpiece among the ten paintings singled out for study is Jan van Eyck’s justly renowned Arnolfini [Wedding] Portrait. But what students are told about it leaves much to be desired. This is what Scholastic Art deems important:
Not a word to indicate that this is a work commemorating the sacrament of marriage–signified by the couple’s joining of hands and the husband’s raising of his other hand. Not a word about the painting’s aura of solemnity, befitting such a sacrament. No mention of the fact that the mirror behind the couple is framed by miniature scenes of Christ’s Passion, further alluding to the painting’s sacred purpose. Nor any suggestion that the little dog so prominently placed below the couple’s joined hands could be both an image of the household pet and a token of their fidelity. Most important, there is no indication of why this work still moves viewers nearly 600 years after its creation. As I argue in Who Says That’s Art?, it is features such as “the sober facial expressions of the young couple, their gesture of joining hands, and the aura of solemn calm in the elegant bedchamber” (all conveyed through van Eyck’s consummate mastery of the art of painting) that “ultimately make it a great work of art, a compelling image that transcends the particular historic moment being represented and conveys something about the gravity of marriage in general.”2[The artist] includes details that provide information about the subjects. The figures wear clothing with thick fur trim, which would have been expensive to own. Many people think the woman looks pregnant. But in reality, she holds the fabric of her dress to show off the costly garment’s length. The way scholars interpret these details has changed over time. For years, people thought the dog was a symbol of loyalty. Today experts believe it is simply the family pet.
One Bright Spot
Dismayed though I was by Scholastic Art’s September 2017 cover article, I applaud the issue’s “Student of the Month” feature. Honoring Grace Lin—an eighth-grade student at the Jay M. Robinson Middle School in Charlotte, North Carolina—it pictures her oil painting Girl with the Bird, which won a gold award in the 2017 Scholastic Art & Writing Awards. A remarkably sensitive and accomplished self-portrait for a girl of only 12 or 13, it is an admirable foil to the avant-garde thrust of “10 Paintings to Know.”3 What inspired it? Not the likes of Picasso, Kandinsky, or Basquiat, but the landscape and art of Italy—in particular, she noted, the “sense of dignity and peace” in Leonardo’s Mona Lisa.
Brava, Grace Lin! Your work would far better serve as a model for your fellow students than that of Scholastic’s poster artists Picasso and Basquiat.
Notes
- The lesson plan provided by Scholastic implicitly lauds Basquiat as a street artist who “gained recognition in the art world through collaborations with established artists such as Andy Warhol. His solo work, which explores ideas of inequality, race, and politics, brought him success and wealth.” As noted above, Basquiat’s exploration of ideas is not at all clear, as even his defenders have admitted. On Warhol’s inflated reputation as an established artist, see “The Apotheosis of Andy Warhol” (Aristos, December 2012). ↩
- Readers who would like to know more about the meaning of this great work should consult Erwin Panofsky, Early Netherlandish Painting: Its Origins and Character (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1964), 201–203. The National Gallery asserts that the painting is not intended as a “record” of the couple’s wedding, but Panofsky (a highly esteemed art historian) cites compelling iconographic evidence that the work aimed to memorialize the couple’s marriage vows. See also H.W. Janson, History of Art, 3d edition, revised and expanded by Anthony F. Janson (New York: Abrams, 1986), 377–378. Addendum: See “Revisiting Jan van Eyck’s Arnolfini ‘Wedding’ Portrait.” ↩
- Unfortunately, it is not clear from the magazine’s account if the painting was done in connection with an art class at the student’s school or as an independent, extracurricular project. ↩
So, you’re back to deleting my posts? Heh.
Well, thanks for covering the ground that we did. It was definitely an improvement! I sincerely hope that some day you’ll feel comfortable facing the difficult challenges that I’ve placed before you.
“You are free to dispute my point by stating what ‘significant values’ you find in such work.”
And when I do state which values I find, then what? Will you believe me, and accept my description as genuine and valid, or will you arbitrarily reject it just as other fans of Ayn Rand have countless times in the past?
Here’s a link to some abstract samples of art that I’ve posted in Objectivst fora many time, and described their meaning and value to me (scroll down to the images and the text that follows):
http://www.objectivistliving.com/forums/index.php?/topic/14839-michelle-marder-kamhis-who-says-thats-art/&do=findComment&comment=223015
Now it’s your turn! Please identify the specific ”artist’s meanings” and “significant values” that are “conveyed” in the images in the lefthand column in this thread’s initial post (ignore the images in the right column):
http://www.objectivistliving.com/forums/index.php?/topic/16100-concerning-essences-especially-in-art/
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
Jonathan,
I don’t have time for protracted argument, but I’ll respond briefly to your two points.
Regarding your responses to the abstract works, do you have any idea if they even approximately correspond to what the artists had in mind? Or do you think the artists’ intentions are irrelevant? In my book I cite quite few famous cases in which the artists’ intended meaning eludes viewers, and my guess is that is true of most, if not all, cases. Can I “prove” it? No. But can you prove I’m mistaken?
Regarding the images you linked to, the “significant value” I see is the beauty of nature, depicted in various aspects by the different artists.
“Many other readers agree with my ‘subjective’ response, however.”
Indeed, many do agree with you, and many don’t. Many people are less aesthetically sensitive than you are, and many people are much more aesthetically sensitive than you are. Unfortunately, you have a history of treating your tastes and sensitivities as the “objective” universal standard and limit, and then of just arbitrarily disregarding others’ responses to art, declaring that they are invalid, and that they are not real (but are instead made-up explanations inspired by the desire to impress artworld authorities), and, most importantly of all, you’ve had a habit of asserting that your personal responses (or lack thereof) represented “objective” standards in determining what is or is not art for everyone.
Now, if your position has changed, then I think that’s fabulous! If you now recognize that you can’t claim to know what depths of meaning others might experience in a work of art based simply on the fact that you and some others personally experienced little or no depth, then kudos to you!
“Ultimately, since subjectivity is inevitably involved in the response to art, the “objective” answer tends to boil down to what philosophers call ‘intersubjectivity’—though I’m sure that answer (or any answer) won’t satisfy you.”
Actually, I find that admission VERY satisfying! It is quite different from your previous claims of making purely “objective” aesthetic judgments!
If you’re claiming to speak for the majority in regard to “intersubjective” interpretations, however, proof would still be required. The mere fact that you feel that your responses are shared by most others doesn’t make it so.
Anyway, it appears that you’re moving away from the position of confirmation bias of believing only those who agree with you and share your tastes, experiences and limitations, and of just outright refusing to believe others’ differing explanations of their responses to art.
It’s been rather disturbing over the years to see many, many people who have been inspired by Ayn Rand’s ideas refusing to believe that each of them is not the absolute pinnacle of aesthetic sensitively and depth. So many times I’ve encountered people who thought that it was a vicious insult for me to suggest the possibility that, as an experienced professional realist artist, I might see and experience more in a work of visual art than they did. I am very encouraged that you appear to be stepping away from sharing their mindset!
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
I can’t answer for the views of other people inspired by Rand’s ideas, and many of them would no doubt vehemently disagree with me on more than one point. Nor do I fully agree with everything Rand said about art. See “Understanding and Appreciating Art.”
“What did that contribution consist of?—’divid[ing] subject matter into small, simplified forms’ and ‘reject[ing] traditional perspective.’”
Heh. And yet you adore Gauguin and Capuletti, despite their obvious simplifying of forms, their deviations from proper anatomy, their (unintentional?) distortions of perspective, and their general lack of artistic mastery. Why the double standards?
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
I don’t adore Capuletti. Nonetheless, I don’t hold that art must be photographically realistic. As I argue in Who Says That’s Art?, artistic imagery, “while not necessarily realistic in style, is intelligible within its cultural context. It embodies, in comprehensible forms, ideas and values that are important to the individuals who create them and have the potential to interest and move others.” The problem with Cubism is that it is largely unintelligible and conveys no significant values.
“I don’t adore Capuletti.”
Oh! My apologies. Apparently I made the mistaken assumption that you did adore Capuletti based on having read Aristos articles which praised him as having been one of the finest painters of the last century. It’s interesting to discover that you may not agree with that very subjective assessment given by your Aristos associate.
My view, as a professional realist artist, is that, by any truly objective standard of judgment, Capuletti was a student-grade artist, and that using his work as an example of great art as identified via “objective” aesthetic judgment is not a good idea.
“Nonetheless, I don’t hold that art must be photographically realistic.”
By what standard do you criticize one artist for his deviations from reality while praising another for his? It seems to be based on nothing but your own personal, subjective tastes. Please identify the objective standard that is used for making such judgments.
“The problem with Cubism is that it is largely unintelligible and conveys no significant values.”
Says who? To whom is it “largely unintelligible”? Where is your objective evidence to back up your assertions about which artworks “convey significant values” and which do not? That proof is missing from your work. All that we have are your bald assertions based on your own personal experiences (or lack thereof) in response to art (along with anecdotal references to a few others who share your limitations). You have not yet OBJECTIVELY shown that ANY work of art has ever met your own criteria.
I know that these are uncomfortable questions, and it can be natural to try to evade them with the excuse that they are personal attacks, but I do not ask them with any hostility. They are legitimate philosophical questions. Please answer them.
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
Jonathan,
You are free to dispute my point by stating what “significant values” you find in such work. Many other readers agree with my “subjective” response, however. Ultimately, since subjectivity is inevitably involved in the response to art, the “objective” answer tends to boil down to what philosophers call “intersubjectivity“—though I’m sure that answer (or any answer) won’t satisfy you.
Please make a list of the 10 pieces of art you would use to teach art history to middle and high schoolers and why. Just curious about your picks.
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
Good question, Courtney. Thanks for asking. I’ll give it some thought and get back to you.
Very good article. I am curious, who is Scholastic to listen to about art and art history?
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
Thank you, Robin. Scholastic Art magazine is published by the Scholastic Corporation for students of visual art in Grades 7-12 and their teachers. It should therefore be of interest to anyone who cares about the quality of art education in our schools.
Great take on a depressing situation, Michelle. Thank you again.
It amazes me that Scholastic Art can even consider some of the ten paintings they feel a student should know—after viewing the amazing, delicate and sensitive portrait by Grace Lin. There are many more students like Grace Lin who crave to know more about periods like the Italian Renaissance. They deserve a more inclusive art education.
The Real Person!
The Real Person!
Indeed!